To frame a government for ourselves."
Dr. Price does not say that the right to do these things exists in
this or in that person, or in this or in that description of persons,
but that it exists in the whole; that it is a right resident in the
nation. Mr. Burke, on the contrary, denies that such a right exists
in the nation, either in whole or in part, or that it exists
anywhere; and, what is still more strange and marvellous, he says:
"that the people of England utterly disclaim such a right, and that
they will resist the practical assertion of it with their lives and
fortunes." That men should take up arms and spend their lives and
fortunes, not to maintain their rights, but to maintain they have not
rights, is an entirely new species of discovery, and suited to the
paradoxical genius of Mr. Burke.
The method which Mr. Burke takes to prove that the people of England
have no such rights, and that such rights do not now exist in the
nation, either in whole or in part, or anywhere at all, is of the
same marvellous and monstrous kind with what he has already said; for
his arguments are that the persons, or the generation of persons, in
whom they did exist, are dead, and with them the right is dead also.
To prove this, he quotes a declaration made by Parliament about a
hundred years ago, to William and Mary, in these words: "The Lords
Spiritual and Temporal, and Commons, do, in the name of the people
aforesaid" (meaning the people of England then living) "most humbly
and faithfully submit themselves, their heirs and posterities, for
Ever." He quotes a clause of another Act of Parliament made in the
same reign, the terms of which he says, "bind us" (meaning the people
of their day), "our heirs and our posterity, to them, their heirs and
posterity, to the end of time."
Mr. Burke conceives his point sufficiently established by producing
those clauses, which he enforces by saying that they exclude the
right of the nation for ever. And not yet content with making such
declarations, repeated over and over again, he farther says, "that if
the people of England possessed such a right before the Revolution"
(which he acknowledges to have been the case, not only in England,
but throughout Europe, at an early period), "yet that the English
Nation did, at the time of the Revolution, most solemnly renounce and
abdicate it, for themselves, and for all their posterity, for ever."
As Mr. Burke occasionally applies the poison drawn from his horrid
principles, not only to the English nation, but to the French
Revolution and the National Assembly, and charges that august,
illuminated and illuminating body of men with the epithet of
usurpers, I shall, sans ceremonie, place another system of principles
in opposition to his.
The English Parliament of 1688 did a certain thing, which, for
themselves and their constituents, they had a right to do, and which
it appeared right should be done. But, in addition to this right,
which they possessed by delegation, they set up another right by
assumption, that of binding and controlling posterity to the end of
time. The case, therefore, divides itself into two parts; the right
which they possessed by delegation, and the right which they set up
by assumption. The first is admitted; but with respect to the second,
I reply: There never did, there never will, and there never can, exist
a Parliament, or any description of men, or any generation of men, in
any country, possessed of the right or the power of binding and
controlling posterity to the "end of time," or of commanding for ever
how the world shall be governed, or who shall govern it; and
therefore all such clauses, acts or declarations by which the makers
of them attempt to do what they have neither the right nor the power
to do, nor the power to execute, are in themselves null and void.
Every age and generation must be as free to act for itself in all
cases as the age and generations which preceded it. The vanity and
presumption of governing beyond the grave is the most ridiculous and
insolent of all tyrannies. Man has no property in man; neither has
any generation a property in the generations which are to follow. The
Parliament or the people of 1688, or of any other period, had no more
right to dispose of the people of the present day, or to bind or to
control them in any shape whatever, than the parliament or the people
of the present day have to dispose of, bind or control those who are
to live a hundred or a thousand years hence. Every generation is, and
must be, competent to all the purposes which its occasions require.
It is the living, and not the dead, that are to be accommodated. When
man ceases to be, his power and his wants cease with him; and having
no longer any participation in the concerns of this world, he has no
longer any authority in directing who shall be its governors, or how
its government shall be organised, or how administered.
I am not contending for nor against any form of government, nor for
nor against any party, here or elsewhere. That which a whole nation
chooses to do it has a right to do. Mr. Burke says, No. Where, then,
does the right exist? I am contending for the rights of the living,
and against their being willed away and controlled and contracted for
by the manuscript assumed authority of the dead, and Mr. Burke is
contending for the authority of the dead over the rights and freedom
of the living. There was a time when kings disposed of their crowns
by will upon their death-beds, and consigned the people, like beasts
of the field, to whatever successor they appointed. This is now so
exploded as scarcely to be remembered, and so monstrous as hardly to
be believed. But the Parliamentary clauses upon which Mr. Burke
builds his political church are of the same nature.
The laws of every country must be analogous to some common principle.
In England no parent or master, nor all the authority of Parliament,
omnipotent as it has called itself, can bind or control the personal
freedom even of an individual beyond the age of twenty-one years. On
what ground of right, then, could the Parliament of 1688, or any
other Parliament, bind all posterity for ever?
Those who have quitted the world, and those who have not yet arrived
at it, are as remote from each other as the utmost stretch of mortal
imagination can conceive. What possible obligation, then, can exist
between them- what rule or principle can be laid down that of two
nonentities, the one out of existence and the other not in, and who
never can meet in this world, the one should control the other to the
end of time?
In England it is said that money cannot be taken out of the pockets
of the people without their consent. But who authorised, or who could
authorise, the Parliament of 1688 to control and take away the
freedom of posterity (who were not in existence to give or to
withhold their consent) and limit and confine their right of acting
in certain cases for ever?
A greater absurdity cannot present itself to the understanding of man
than what Mr. Burke offers to his readers.
1 comment